Can Retribution Justify the Revocation of Supervised Release? Courts Disagree.




Legal Sidebari

Can Retribution Justify the Revocation of
Supervised Release? Courts Disagree.

Updated June 17, 2024
What are the legitimate reasons that a government may subject an individual to criminal punishment?
Western penological theory and American legal history generally identify four principled bases for
criminal punishment: retribution, deterrence, incapacitation, and rehabilitation. The Sentencing Reform
Act (SRA) requires federal courts to impose an initial sentence that reflects these purposes of punishment.
The SRA also authorizes federal courts to sentence defendants to supervised release, encompassing a set
of conditions that the defendant must comply with upon release from prison for a period of time (or, for
some offenses, for up to life). A defendant’s compliance with these conditions is “supervised” or
monitored by a federal probation officer. If a defendant violates a condition, the court may revoke the
supervised release and send the defendant back to prison, among other things. The SRA lists deterrence,
incapacitation, and rehabilitation among the factors that a judge must consider in making these revocation
determinations. The SRA does not, however, expressly include retribution as one such factor.
The federal appeals courts disagree as to whether, and to what extent, retribution may justify the
revocation of supervised release in light of this statutory omission. On one side of the divide, the U.S.
Courts of Appeals for the First, Second, Third, Sixth, and Seventh Circuits have held that federal courts
may consider retribution in making revocation decisions. On the other side, the Fourth, Fifth, Ninth, and
Tenth Circuits have concluded that courts either may not consider retribution in these decisions at all or
may consider it only to a limited degree.
This Sidebar summarizes the four purposes of punishment, including retribution; offers an overview of
supervised release; and summarizes the aforementioned split. The Sidebar concludes with congressional
considerations.
The Purposes of Punishment
“[T]he goals of penal sanctions that have been recognized as legitimate,” according to the Supreme Court,
are “retribution, deterrence, incapacitation, and rehabilitation.” In general, retribution is the principle that
an individual should be punished because they deserve punishment. This theory of punishment is most
associated with philosopher Immanuel Kant, who wrote that punishment “must in all cases be imposed
only because the individual on whom it is inflicted has committed a [c]rime.” Retributive theory has
Congressional Research Service
https://crsreports.congress.gov
LSB10929
CRS Legal Sidebar
Prepared for Members and
Committees of Congress




Congressional Research Service
2
multiple strands. The “hard” form of retribution provides that an individual who violates the law invites
and deserves social vengeance or retaliation. This understanding of retribution is restated colloquially in
the phrase “an eye for an eye.” Thomas Jefferson similarly characterized retribution as providing that
“whoever . . . shall maim another, or shall disfigure him . . . shall be maimed or disfigured in like sort.”
Other forms of retribution are not necessarily expressions of, or channels for, social anger, but are rather
dispassionate responses to the actions of the lawbreaker. Under this view, retribution is seen as a
reflection of the social contract in that an individual who voluntarily violates the law is owed punishment.
In this sense, retribution furthers several goals, including respecting the moral choices of the individual,
restoring the equilibrium upset by the wrongdoer’s attempt to gain an advantage over others through
unlawful means, and ensuring that shared laws are enforced and not ignored.
Critical distinctions exist between the retributive and the utilitarian models of punishment (the latter of
which encompasses deterrence, incapacitation, and rehabilitation). The retributivist model is concerned
about the nature of the past criminal conduct, focusing on the culpability of the defendant and the severity
of the harms inflicted. This past criminal conduct is sufficient for the retributivist to believe that
punishment is warranted. By contrast, the utilitarian is interested in what can be gained prospectively by
the imposition of punishment. The commission of a crime is therefore insufficient to impose punishment;
there must also be a future social benefit for punishment to be justified. That is, in reaching punishment
decisions, the retributivist approach generally is backward-looking and the utilitarian forward-looking.
The three utilitarian models of punishment—deterrence, incapacitation, and rehabilitation—have a
common thread in that each justifies punishment if there is a social good or benefit to such punishment.
First, deterrence theory, writes philosopher Jeremy Bentham, works “towards the prevention of like acts.”
That is, deterrence aims to make sure that the cost from punishment is greater than the advantages of
crime, such that the self-interested actor will decide against committing the crime. Put differently,
deterrence ensures that crime is not “worth it.” There are two types of deterrence: specific deterrence,
where the punishment is designed to disincentivize a particular defendant from committing “like acts,”
and general deterrence, where the punishment is aimed at disincentivizing the public from committing
“like acts.” Second, incapacitation removes the individual from society, physically eliminating the risk
that the individual may commit additional crimes against others. Third, rehabilitation seeks to reform the
individual such that they will be better able, upon release, to stay within the bounds of the law.
In 1984, Congress enacted the SRA, which established the U.S. Sentencing Commission and charged this
new agency with promulgating the first-ever federal sentencing guidelines. The SRA also codified the
purposes of punishment for violations of federal criminal law—18 U.S.C. § 3553(a)(2)(A) (corresponding
with retribution); 18 U.S.C. § 3553(a)(2)(B) (corresponding with deterrence); 18 U.S.C. § 3553(a)(2)(C)
(corresponding with incapacitation); and 18 U.S.C. § 3553(a)(2)(D) (corresponding with rehabilitation)—
and instructed federal judges to impose an initial sentence that would be “sufficient, but not greater than
necessary,” to reflect these purposes.
Differences Between Retributive and Utilitarian Models
The models of justification for punishment described above can lead to different sentencing outcomes.
Kant illustrated one distinction in writing that, if an individual on death row were the last member of a
dissolving society, the individual still should be executed in accordance with the retributive theory
because the punishment remains his moral desert regardless of the presence of, or benefits to, other
people. The differences between retributive and utilitarian models are also evident in judicial and
administrative settings. For example, the Seventh Circuit observed that, from a retributivist standpoint, a
defendant’s diminished capacity would justify a lighter sentence because an individual with diminished
capacity may have minimal ability to appreciate their conduct and thus may have minimal culpability. By
contrast, diminished capacity may warrant a longer sentence under a utilitarian perspective, the court
explained, because an individual with diminished capacity may have minimal ability to conform their


Congressional Research Service
3
conduct to the law and thus may require longer incapacitation. When the Sentencing Commission
developed the initial federal sentencing guidelines, the agency addressed the “philosophical dilemma” of
attempting to reconcile the retributive and utilitarian models by adopting an empirical approach based on
past sentencing practices. The Commission reasoned that judges issuing those sentences necessarily
considered the purposes of punishment and thus past sentences embodied the principled justifications for
sentencing.
Supervised Release in the Federal System
The SRA authorizes, and in some instances requires, federal courts to impose supervised release on an
individual convicted of a federal crime. In general, supervised release comprises a set of conditions that a
federal defendant must comply with upon release from prison. Supervised release is distinct from
probation and parole. While all three may involve the imposition of behavioral conditions, probation may
be imposed with no attendant term of imprisonment, parole may be imposed to replace some (i.e., the
unexpired part) of a term of imprisonment, and supervised release begins only after a defendant fully
serves a term of imprisonment (minus any good time credits). Of the three, only supervised release and
probation remain options for sentencing judges; the SRA prospectively abolished parole for federal
crimes to promote certainty, or “truth,” in sentencing.
Supervised release is required if the defendant is convicted of specific crimes, such as certain drug or sex
offenses. Where supervised release is not mandated by statute, a court has discretion as to whether to
impose a term of supervised release. In practice, federal courts impose supervised release in virtually all
cases.
The SRA identifies conditions of supervised release that are mandatory and discretionary. Mandatory
conditions include requirements that the defendant must not commit another offense; must submit to drug
testing, unless excepted; and must comply with federal sex offender registration conditions, if applicable.
A court also may impose “standard” or “special” discretionary conditions, such as reporting to the
probation officer; not leaving the jurisdiction without approval; allowing home visits by the probation
officer; obtaining full-time employment; not possessing firearms; and receiving substance use or mental
health treatment. The length of a term of supervised release depends on the crime of conviction and
generally may span one, three, or five years, with the possibility of early termination after one year. For
certain serious offenses, however, supervised release may be imposed for longer periods, including life.
Compliance with conditions is monitored by a federal probation officer. Depending on the circumstances,
a federal court may terminate, extend, or revoke the term of supervised release. If a supervisee violates a
condition, 18 U.S.C. § 3583(e)(3) provides for revocation, stating that a “court may, after considering the
factors set forth in [18 U.S.C.] section 3553(a)(1), (a)(2)(B), (a)(2)(C), (a)(2)(D) . . . revoke a term of
supervised release, and require the defendant to serve in prison all or part of the term of supervised
release” (with some limits). Section 3553(a)(1) includes the “nature and circumstances of the offense,”
and the other factors that are listed correspond to the utilitarian considerations of deterrence,
incapacitation, and rehabilitation. Absent from the enumerated considerations is 18 U.S.C.
§ 3553(a)(2)(A), the purpose of punishment corresponding with retribution.
The Judicial Disagreement
The U.S. Courts of Appeals are split as to whether retribution may be considered in supervised-release
revocation decisions. On one hand, the First, Second, Third, Sixth, and Seventh Circuits have held that,
despite the omission of Section 3553(a)(2)(A) as a required revocation consideration listed in Section
3583(e)(3), judges retain discretion to take all four purposes of punishment, including retribution, into
account as part of the revocation process. In justifying this interpretation, the First Circuit explained its
view that the reference in Section 3583(e)(3) to certain enumerated factors does not forbid or foreclose


Congressional Research Service
4
consideration of other Section 3553(a) factors. Moreover, the Second Circuit has indicated that,
practically speaking, consideration of the enumerated factors, including the “nature and circumstances of
the offense,” necessarily requires consideration of the seriousness of the offense, a retributive factor. The
Second Circuit further suggested that the legislative history of the SRA confirms that the “nature” of the
offense encompasses retributive considerations. The Sixth Circuit likewise indicated that some of the
purposes of revocation—to help the individual learn respect for the rule of law and to sanction the
individual for the violation—are retributive in character. The Sixth Circuit also pointed out that Congress
did not expressly limit supervised-release revocation decisions to the Section 3583 factors, for example
by stating that “only” these factors may be considered.
On the other hand, the Fourth, Fifth, Ninth, and Tenth Circuits have held that the Section 3553(a) factor
corresponding to retribution is either forbidden in supervised-release revocation decisions or is entitled to
less weight in such decisions. These courts interpret the omission of Section 3553(a)(2)(A) in Section
3583(e)(3) to indicate Congress’s deliberate intent to remove retribution from the universe of what a
federal court may consider at the revocation stage. For example, the Fifth and Ninth Circuits favorably
cited the canon of construction that, if Congress uses language in one section of a statute and omits that
language in another section of the same statute, it may be presumed that the omission was intentional.
That said, while the Fourth, Fifth, and Tenth Circuits have held that retribution may not be considered at
all in this context, the Ninth Circuit has appeared to take a more nuanced approach, indicating that
reliance on an omitted factor “as a primary basis for a revocation sentence” would be improper.
Congressional Considerations
The circuit split regarding retributive considerations in supervised-release revocation decisions exists
against the backdrop of a broader policy debate. At least one scholar has argued in favor of using only
utilitarian factors in revocation decisions. By contrast, the Sentencing Commission has been cited in
support of the opposite position, on the ground that it “take[s] into account the seriousness of the violation
of supervised release by setting lengthier guideline ranges for offenses classified as more serious.” That
said, the Commission also has suggested that courts in supervised release revocation proceedings should
consider the purposes of punishment “except” for the factor corresponding with retribution.
Congress may seek to consider whether to address the ongoing confusion and disagreement given its
potential ramifications. The prevalence of supervised release violations has “varied considerably” across
federal districts, and the circuit split reflects that different jurisdictions apply different revocation
standards when violations do occur. These disparities may have real-life consequences, as a federal
sentence of imprisonment is followed by a term of supervised release in 99.1% of cases and more than
109,000 individuals are currently under supervised release. If desired, Congress could address this
situation by amending Section 3583(e) to make clear that the sentencing factor corresponding to
retribution either may or may not be considered in supervised release revocation decisions. Doing so
would likely yield uniformity in a common and consequential component of the federal criminal justice
system.



Congressional Research Service
5
Author Information

Dave S. Sidhu

Legislative Attorney




Disclaimer
This document was prepared by the Congressional Research Service (CRS). CRS serves as nonpartisan shared staff
to congressional committees and Members of Congress. It operates solely at the behest of and under the direction of
Congress. Information in a CRS Report should not be relied upon for purposes other than public understanding of
information that has been provided by CRS to Members of Congress in connection with CRS’s institutional role.
CRS Reports, as a work of the United States Government, are not subject to copyright protection in the United
States. Any CRS Report may be reproduced and distributed in its entirety without permission from CRS. However,
as a CRS Report may include copyrighted images or material from a third party, you may need to obtain the
permission of the copyright holder if you wish to copy or otherwise use copyrighted material.

LSB10929 · VERSION 2 · UPDATED